ورود به حساب

نام کاربری گذرواژه

گذرواژه را فراموش کردید؟ کلیک کنید

حساب کاربری ندارید؟ ساخت حساب

ساخت حساب کاربری

نام نام کاربری ایمیل شماره موبایل گذرواژه

برای ارتباط با ما می توانید از طریق شماره موبایل زیر از طریق تماس و پیامک با ما در ارتباط باشید


09117307688
09117179751

در صورت عدم پاسخ گویی از طریق پیامک با پشتیبان در ارتباط باشید

دسترسی نامحدود

برای کاربرانی که ثبت نام کرده اند

ضمانت بازگشت وجه

درصورت عدم همخوانی توضیحات با کتاب

پشتیبانی

از ساعت 7 صبح تا 10 شب

دانلود کتاب The Kyoto School’s Takeover of Hegel: Nishida, Nishitani, and Tanabe Remake the Philosophy of Spirit

دانلود کتاب تسلط مکتب کیوتو بر هگل: نیشیدا، نیشیتانی و تانابه فلسفه روح را بازسازی می کنند.

The Kyoto School’s Takeover of Hegel: Nishida, Nishitani, and Tanabe Remake the Philosophy of Spirit

مشخصات کتاب

The Kyoto School’s Takeover of Hegel: Nishida, Nishitani, and Tanabe Remake the Philosophy of Spirit

دسته بندی: فلسفه
ویرایش:  
نویسندگان:   
سری:  
ISBN (شابک) : 0739146882, 9780739146880 
ناشر: Lexington Books 
سال نشر: 2010 
تعداد صفحات: 234 
زبان: English 
فرمت فایل : PDF (درصورت درخواست کاربر به PDF، EPUB یا AZW3 تبدیل می شود) 
حجم فایل: 5 مگابایت 

قیمت کتاب (تومان) : 38,000



کلمات کلیدی مربوط به کتاب تسلط مکتب کیوتو بر هگل: نیشیدا، نیشیتانی و تانابه فلسفه روح را بازسازی می کنند.: بودیسم، دالایی لاما، تاریخ، ماهایانا، مناسک و تمرین، نوشته های مقدس، تراوادا، تبتی، ذن، دین و معنویت، شرق، بودیسم، هند، تائوئیسم، ذن، فلسفه، سیاست و علوم اجتماعی، متافیزیک و فلسفه اجتماعی، علوم، متافیزیک، فلسفه، علوم انسانی، کتاب های درسی جدید، مستعمل و اجاره ای، بوتیک تخصصی



ثبت امتیاز به این کتاب

میانگین امتیاز به این کتاب :
       تعداد امتیاز دهندگان : 16


در صورت تبدیل فایل کتاب The Kyoto School’s Takeover of Hegel: Nishida, Nishitani, and Tanabe Remake the Philosophy of Spirit به فرمت های PDF، EPUB، AZW3، MOBI و یا DJVU می توانید به پشتیبان اطلاع دهید تا فایل مورد نظر را تبدیل نمایند.

توجه داشته باشید کتاب تسلط مکتب کیوتو بر هگل: نیشیدا، نیشیتانی و تانابه فلسفه روح را بازسازی می کنند. نسخه زبان اصلی می باشد و کتاب ترجمه شده به فارسی نمی باشد. وبسایت اینترنشنال لایبرری ارائه دهنده کتاب های زبان اصلی می باشد و هیچ گونه کتاب ترجمه شده یا نوشته شده به فارسی را ارائه نمی دهد.


توضیحاتی در مورد کتاب تسلط مکتب کیوتو بر هگل: نیشیدا، نیشیتانی و تانابه فلسفه روح را بازسازی می کنند.

تسخیر هگل توسط مکتب کیوتو: نیشیدا، نیشیتانی و تانابه، فلسفه روح را بازسازی می کنند تحلیل عمیق پیتر سوارز از ادغام ایده آلیسم فلسفی غرب توسط مکتب کیوتو با سنت های مذهبی ژاپنی است. سورس تلاش‌های مکتب را برای توسعه آموزه‌ی نیستی مطلق با استفاده از دیالکتیک خودآگاهی هگل دنبال می‌کند. دیالکتیک هگل در کار سه شخصیت اصلی مکتب -نیشیدا کیتارو، نیشیتانی کیجی و تانابه هاجیمه- نقش سازنده ای ایفا می کند، اما ادغام بسیاری از جنبه های آن با دیدگاه نو بودایی آنها دشوار است. سورس نشان می دهد که چگونه این دشواری در دوگانگی سه فیلسوف نسبت به هگل آشکار می شود: آنها نه تنها طرفداران او، بلکه منتقدان صریح او نیز هستند. انتقاد آنها به خودی خود کم مشکل نیست. شناسایی ایده های ظاهراً هگلی که توسط نیشیدا، نیشیتانی و تانابه تقبیح شده است، اغلب در فلسفه او دشوار است. از سوی دیگر، بسیاری از تزهای خودشان که در مخالفت صریح با هگل مطرح می‌کنند، در واقع کاملاً با آموزه‌های او سازگار است. با توجه به اهمیت محوری هگل برای مکتب کیوتو، سورس نشان می‌دهد که چگونه این خوانش‌های نادرست نشان‌دهنده مشکلی در انسجام جهان‌بینی گسترده‌تر این مکتب است. تسلط مکتب کیوتو بر هگل نشان می‌دهد که چگونه می‌توان این مشکل را کاهش داد و فلسفه نیستی مدرسه را مؤثرتر از امروز کرد.


توضیحاتی درمورد کتاب به خارجی

The Kyoto School's Takeover of Hegel: Nishida, Nishitani, and Tanabe Remake the Philosophy of Spirit is Peter Suares' in-depth analysis of the Kyoto School's integration of Western philosophical idealism with Japanese religious traditions. Suares traces the School's attempts to develop a doctrine of absolute nothingness using Hegel's dialectic of self-consciousness. Hegel's dialectic plays a formative role in the work of the three principal figures of the School―Nishida Kitaro, Nishitani Keiji, and Tanabe Hajime―yet many of its aspects are difficult to integrate with their neo-Buddhist outlook. Suares shows how this difficulty manifests itself in the ambivalence of the three philosophers toward Hegel: they are not only his adherents, but also his outspoken critics. Their criticism itself is no less problematic. The ostensibly Hegelian ideas denounced by Nishida, Nishitani, and Tanabe are often difficult to identify in his philosophy. On the other hand, many of their own theses, which they advance in express opposition to Hegel, are in fact quite compatible with his teachings. Given the pivotal importance of Hegel to the Kyoto School, Suares demonstrates how these misreadings signal a problem with the coherence of the School's broader worldview. The Kyoto School's Takeover of Hegel suggests how this problem could have been mitigated, making the School's philosophy of nothingness more effective than it is today.



فهرست مطالب

One example of the way Hegel’s ideas took hold far from his native Germany is their reception in modem Japan. His Phenomenology of Spirit1 was among the first few books in Western philosophy brought back to Japan by two scholars, Nishi Amane (1829-1897) and Tsuda Mamichi (1829-1903), from their trip to Europe in 1862.2 From 1877 on, American educator and orientalist Ernest Fenollosa (1853-1908) taught courses on the German philosopher at Tokyo Imperial University. Since the late nineteenth century, Hegel’s works have been translated into Japanese in advance of Kant’s, and the list of Japanese publications on his philosophy now fills over three hundred pages. The pace of publication accelerated since the hundredth anniversary of Hegel’s death in 1931, the year around which the growing popularity of his philosophy of history began to eclipse the interest in Neo-Kantianism dominating Japan’s philosophical circles until that time.

   There are several reasons for Japan’s fascination with Hegel. In the first few decades following the Meiji Restoration of 1868, the country held German culture in deep esteem and accorded it a place of honor in the state curriculum. Hegel was seen naturally as a major representative of German thought. Another reason lies in the scope and the character of his achievement. Hegel’s philosophy took upon itself the task of interpreting, according to its principles, everything known to man. It strived to provide a complete account of reality and to build up that account into a system. This could not but strike a sympathetic chord with the Japanese people, fond as they are of the tangible and the phenomenal, and please their sense for organization and exhaustiveness. Of appeal to the Japanese public was also Hegel’s theory of moral substance and objective spirit manifested in social forms. The philosopher’s appreciation for the socializing power of the community and its traditions, palpable in that theory, found resonance in the Japanese propensity to derive individual identity from the group and the community of one’s belonging. The social orientation of the Japanese held firm despite their avid but superficial experimentation with Western individualism and “subjectivity” since about the turn of the twentieth century. From the other side of the globe, Hegel’s views offered a soothing reassurance for a core Japanese value.

   While engaged in patient examination of one temporal aspect of reality after another, Hegel never lost sight of the ubiquitous presence of the eternal. That enduring focus was no less characteristic of his political philosophy, making it agreeable to the absolutist tendencies of the Japanese state of that time. Prevailing over numerous liberal subcurrents, the overall trend of early twentieth-century Japan was conservative. It favored the strengthening of national polity (kokutai), an immutable structure of the racially homogeneous family-state with the divine Imperial household at its center. Hegel’s politically conservative view of the absolute spirit developing through history toward the perfection of its own consciousness manifested in the state was syntonic with that ideology.3 Ironically, Hegel’s principles (recast in the Marxist form) were exploited in equal measure by the Marxist foes of the Japanese establishment.

   Japan’s Buddhist heritage fostered its appreciation for the affinities between Hegelian and Mahāyāna metaphysics. For Hegel, all beings are determined by otherness. More plainly, everything finite is by nature relative to something else; a thing is defined through the complex of its finite relationships. This quality was perceived to accord with the Mahāyāna notion of emptiness (śūnyatā), according to which things have no inherent nature or reality, except in a conventional sense. In particular, the Kegon school of Buddhism postulates mutual identity of phenomena that, while appearing to be possessed of independent existences, lack fixed boundaries and interpenetrate. Having their identities grounded in something other than themselves, yet maintaining their individuality, finite beings in both views can be characterized as both transcendent and immanent to themselves.

   One also notes the inner unrest and multiperspectivism of Hegel’s dialectic, which draws upon the notion of an ever-shifting and fluid nature of conceptual determinations. The dynamic character of dialectic helps loosen the separation between the relative and the absolute. In that, it brings to mind the three-truths (santai) teaching of Tendai Buddhism, which attempts to reconcile two opposite views—one that absolutely rejects the notion of an inherent reality of phenomena, and one that accepts them as provisionally realby postulating a middle way in which each view determines and offsets the other.4

   In its impact, Hege’s thought was not limited to delighting the Japanese public with its affinities with their cultural tradition; it became a powerful force shaping the nascent Japanese philosophy. This is particularly evident in the case of the Kyoto School, a collective name given to a succession of academics active at Kyoto University through a good part of the last century. Although the Kyoto Scholars did not form a school or organization in a formal sense, they shared a neo-Buddhist outlook and adherence to the tenet of absolute nothingness, an outgrowth of the Mahāyāna notion of emptiness. Hegel’s ideas and method played a role in forming their thinking, both directly and mediated through later Western figures captivated by Hegel. Nishida Kitarō (1870-1945), the first and foremost representative of the Kyoto School, is sometimes described squarely as a Hegelian. Hegel’s philosophical idealism also reverberates deeply in the work of many of Nishida’s disciples. To be sure, had their reception of Hegel taken the form of simple adoption or imitation, it would not be of much interest to us today. What makes the Kyoto School’s enchantment with Hegel intriguing is its strongly negative undercurrent. In contrast to the assiduousness with which the Kyoto Scholars assimilated Hegel’s philosophy, they were not always disposed to acknowledging their indebtedness to his ideas. Their overt attitudes toward Hegel ranged from willing embrace to contemptuous rejection, often shifting from one to the other within a single essay, if not in the course of a few pages. To ascribe these fluctuations to confusion or a lack of logical rigor would be a mistake; it would fail to do justice to the complexity of the motives involved. By taking a stand on Hegel, the Buddhist-leaning Nishida and his disciples were confronting a major current of Western intellectual history belonging to—all similarities notwithstanding—a very different tradition. When responding to it critically, they were defining their own distinctive position. Their ambivalence toward Hegel is a sign of self-assertiveness, and at the same time, of an unsettled attitude toward the West. A study of their responses to Hegel offers a glimpse into that attitude. Beyond that, it affords a vantage point from which to view their own philosophy of true reality and the diverse “dialectics” through which they define our place within it.




نظرات کاربران